Genetics and Evolution
Resources

 email page    print page

All Topic Reviews
A Companion to GenethicsA Companion to GenethicsA Cooperative SpeciesA Mind So RareA Natural History of RapeAcquiring GenomesAdapting MindsAgeing, Health and CareAlas, Poor DarwinAn Introduction to Evolutionary EthicsAncient Bodies, Modern LivesAnimal ArchitectsAping MankindAre We Hardwired?Bang!BehavingBeyond EvolutionBeyond GeneticsBlood MattersBody BazaarBoneBrain Evolution and CognitionBrain StormBrave New BrainBrave New WorldsChoosing ChildrenCloneCloningConceptual Issues in Evolutionary BiologyConsciousness EvolvingContemporary Debates in Philosophy of BiologyControlling Our DestiniesCooperation and Its EvolutionCreatures of AccidentDarwin Loves YouDarwin's Brave New WorldDarwin's Gift to Science and ReligionDarwin's UniverseDarwin's WormsDarwinian ConservatismDarwinian PsychiatryDarwinism and its DiscontentsDarwinism as ReligionDebating DesignDecoding DarknessDefenders of the TruthDo We Still Need Doctors?Doubting Darwin?Early WarningEngineering the Human GermlineEnhancing EvolutionEnoughEntwined LivesEthical Issues in Human CloningEthical Issues in the New GeneticsEvil GenesEvolutionEvolutionEvolution and Human BehaviorEvolution and Human BehaviorEvolution and Human Sexual BehaviorEvolution and LearningEvolution and ReligionEvolution and the Human MindEvolution in MindEvolution, Gender, and RapeEvolution: The Modern SynthesisEvolutionary Ethics and Contemporary BiologyEvolutionary Origins of MoralityEvolutionary PsychiatryEvolutionary PsychologyEvolutionary Psychology and ViolenceEvolutionary Psychology as Maladapted PsychologyExploding the Gene MythFaces of Huntington'sFlesh of My FleshFrom Chance to ChoiceFrom Darwin to HitlerGenesGenes in ConflictGenes on the CouchGenes, Environment, and PsychopathologyGenes, Environment, and PsychopathologyGenes, Women, EqualityGenetic Nature/CultureGenetic PoliticsGenetic ProspectsGenetic ProspectsGenetic SecretsGenetics of Criminal and Antisocial BehaviourGenetics of Mental DisordersGenetics of Original SinGenetics of Original SinGenomeGenomeGenome: Updated EditionGenomes and What to Make of ThemGlowing GenesHow Women Got Their Curves and Other Just-So StoriesHuman CloningHuman Evolution, Reproduction, and MoralityImproving Nature?In Our Own ImageIn Pursuit of the GeneIn the Name of GodIngenious GenesInheritanceInside the Human GenomeInside the O'BriensIntegrating Evolution and DevelopmentIntelligence, Race, and GeneticsIs Human Nature Obsolete?Language OriginsLess Than HumanLiberal EugenicsLiving with Our GenesMaking Genes, Making WavesMaking Sense of EvolutionMan As The PrayerMean GenesMenMood GenesMoral OriginsMothers and OthersNature Via NurtureNever Let Me GoNot By Genes AloneOf Flies, Mice, and MenOn the Origin of StoriesOrigin of MindOrigins of Human NatureOrigins of PsychopathologyOur Posthuman FuturePhilosophy of BiologyPlaying God?Playing God?Portraits of Huntington'sPrimates and PhilosophersPromiscuityPsychiatric Genetics and GenomicsPsychologyQuality of Life and Human DifferenceRe-creating MedicineRedesigning HumansResearch Advances in Genetics and GenomicsResponsible GeneticsResponsible GeneticsScience, Seeds and CyborgsSex and WarSociological Perspectives on the New GeneticsStrange BedfellowsStrange BehaviorSubjects of the WorldSubordination and DefeatThe Age of EmpathyThe Agile GeneThe Ape and the Sushi MasterThe Biotech CenturyThe Blank SlateThe Book of LifeThe Bridge to HumanityThe Case Against PerfectionThe Case for PerfectionThe Case of the Female OrgasmThe Century of the GeneThe Common ThreadThe Concept of the Gene in Development and EvolutionThe Debated MindThe Double-Edged HelixThe Epidemiology of SchizophreniaThe Ethics of Human CloningThe Evolution of CooperationThe Evolution of MindThe Evolution of MindThe Evolved ApprenticeThe Evolving WorldThe Fact of EvolutionThe Folly of FoolsThe Future of Human NatureThe God GeneThe Immortal Life of Henrietta LacksThe Impact of the GeneThe Innate MindThe Innate MindThe Innate Mind: Volume 3The Limits and Lies of Human Genetic ResearchThe Lives of the BrainThe Maladapted MindThe Meme MachineThe Misunderstood GeneThe Moral, Social, and Commercial Imperatives of Genetic Testing and ScreeningThe Most Dangerous AnimalThe New Genetic MedicineThe Nurture AssumptionThe Origin and Evolution of CulturesThe Origins of FairnessThe Paradoxical PrimateThe Perfect BabyThe Robot's RebellionThe Selfish GeneThe Shape of ThoughtThe Shattered SelfThe Stem Cell ControversyThe Story WithinThe Stuff of LifeThe Talking ApeThe Temperamental ThreadThe Terrible GiftThe Theory of OptionsThe Top 10 Myths About EvolutionThe Triple HelixThe Triumph of SociobiologyThe Woman Who Walked into the SeaTwinsUnderstanding CloningUnderstanding the GenomeUnnatural SelectionUnto OthersUp From DragonsWar Against the WeakWhat Genes Can't DoWhat It Means to Be 98 Percent ChimpanzeeWho Owns YouWhose View of Life?Why Evolution Is TrueWhy Think? WondergenesWrestling with Behavioral GeneticsYour Genetic Destiny

Related Topics
The Triple HelixReview - The Triple Helix
The Soul of Bioethics
by Lisa Bellantoni
Palgrave Macmillan, 2011
Review by William A. Bauer
May 14th 2013 (Volume 17, Issue 20)

In The Triple Helix: The Soul of Bioethics, Lisa Bellantoni explores philosophical theories of persons and their moral worth within the context of various bioethical issues such as end-of-life decision-making, cloning, and biological enhancements to human capacities. The Triple Helix has three major aims distributed over nine chapters. After stating these aims, this review explains them in some detail while offering critical reflections about them, and concludes with an overall appraisal of Bellantoni's book.

Bellantoni first identifies, describes, and criticizes two dominant views about the nature of persons: the culture of rights and the culture of life, or the "cult of rights" and the "cult of life" (pp. 2-3). Second, she develops her own view, arguing that we are essentially embodied agents with inherent privacy, and that bodily health and function are natural values. While pursing these first two aims, Bellantoni frequently contrasts the two cults' views with her own view. Third, she draws out the implications of the three views for a host of bioethical issues.

The cult of life holds that persons are immaterial souls of inherent moral worth, but contingently embodied. This view has its philosophical pedigree in the work of Plato and others. The value of (human) life is inviolable and untouchable, and must be preserved at all costs, even against the will of the one who has, or is, the soul in question. So, for example, voluntary active euthanasia is typically not permitted on this view. But Bellantoni contends that medical or biotechnological interventions involving humans should be of no concern to cult of life advocates, because such choices and events do not matter to the worth of persons on their view: "[…] the soul once embodied can neither increase nor decrease its absolute worth through its actions" (p. 82). However, it is a good bet that many followers of the cult of life would disagree. In particular, believers of various religious creeds who are part of the cult of life tend to believe that the worth of a person (an immaterial soul) necessarily depends, at least partly, on the choices and events that person makes in his or her embodied life. Embodiment is part of a maturation process and test for the person that is a soul.

The cult of rights maintains that "[…] our absolute moral worth attends our unfettered autonomy" (p. 5). This view has its philosophical pedigree, in different manifestations, in the work of Immanuel Kant and Jean-Paul Sartre. We are self-authoring, self-legislating individuals, but we can only enact these powers from a position of autonomy executed under fairly strict conditions that are not always achievable. When we do not possess autonomy (or are incapable of fully exercising it), our choices are not authoritative.

Bellantoni points out what are, at least, necessary conditions for personhood and individual moral worth on the two cults' views (having a soul, or having autonomy). But this is where representatives of the cult of life and the cult of rights can challenge her characterization of their views: they could argue that, although these conditions are necessary, they are not sufficient to determine the moral worth of a person. This is because, as advocates of the two cults might argue, lived experiences and choices influence the worth of persons, as indicated above with regard to various religious views that follow the cult of life. If they took this strategy as a response, they could thereby coopt some of the features of Bellantoni's own view of persons and their value, which we now come to.

Bellantoni's view issues a re-understanding of the limits and recommendations of bioethics, opening many more possibilities than either the cult of rights or cult of life allows. Bellantoni aims to put the bio firmly in bioethics: no transcendent properties allowed, because we are biological entities with natural biological goods that ground our moral worth. There are two aspects to her view, one about how we come to be, and one about what we are. Both are connected to what is of value in living. First, what we are: Bellantoni emphasizes the importance of the "cultivation of individual human lives in their particulars – their bodily interiority, their psychic subjectivity, their agency – particulars apart from which persons would require no more defense" (p. 6). Our personal nature presents boundaries against others. However, the particular features of our personal natures come into being via our connections and relations to others. The creation of persons is a process. So the second aspect of her view is this: "Persons are born of embodied persons […] and embody others' genes, others' histories, others' values, and others' affects" (p. 5). It follows that "All of us are […] person makers" (p. 6), given our capacities to reproduce, influence, and value others.

          What is of fundamental value to us, given our embodied nature, is not an immaterial soul (cult of life) or a transcendent property of autonomy (cult of rights), but bodily health and functionality (p. 191). These serve to ground the "[…] bodily interiority, first-person subjectivity, and agency apart from which human organisms could not value distinctively human lives at all" (p. 191). Moreover, persons and their value are in biological motion, so to speak, unlike the views promulgated by the cult of rights and cult of life. "Goodness, like health, is simply not a static, transcendent property that we bear by definition," Bellantoni contends (p. 222). Furthermore, her view calls for us not to just maintain healthfulness as a natural good, but to improve and enhance it through biotechnological innovations (p. 193).

In contrast to the cults of rights and the cult of life, Bellantoni's view brings our agency and personhood down to earth. She draws our attention to the phrase "human person" (p. 206). For the cults of life and rights, what is important is what "person" refers to--an immaterial soul or an autonomous being. But for Bellantoni, what is important is what "human" refers to: our distinctive biological nature and private experiences in relation to others that take shape in living. Thus, she offers an embodied theory of agency, and thus an embodied theory of human value. The dominating themes of Bellantoni's view are tied up in a "triple helix" consisting of time, love, and memory (p. 210). These three features, which Bellantoni weaves throughout her monograph, are inextricably tied to our personal and interpersonal experiences. Only through "[…] an intertwining of time, love, and memory, may we make of human persons objects of moral regard and subjects of moral agency" (p. 211). It is in these features, not the "timeless ideals" (p. 211) of the cult of rights and the cult of life, that our agency and value are found.

The view of life and value one takes clearly has profound implications for how to assess various bioethics issues. The cult of rights and the cult of life--because they separate what is essential to persons from their lived, embodied experience, and because they classify persons as something that transcends their biological constitution--end  up committing some of the same errors, according to Bellantoni. Both cults are paternalistic, allowing others to control an individual's life at certain junctures: for example, at points where life may not be valuable to a particular person anymore, the cult of life insists it is, and at points where that person does not make choices under autonomous conditions, the cult of rights insists upon denying that person the right to exercise his or her will. Bellantoni's view rejects these paternalistic outcomes.

There is much to like in Bellantoni's book. Although it will appeal mostly to philosophers with interests in bioethics, those coming with a philosophical bent from psychology, sociology, and other fields should find value in it too. Bellantoni successfully pushes the debate forward on a variety of bioethics issues through the lens of different conceptions of personhood, while simultaneously engaging in a kind of meta-bioethics by critiquing current bioethics practices.

However, some aspects of Bellantoni's discussion are overly drawn out and repetitive, and the intricate interweaving of the book's three aims is occasionally dizzying. Additionally, some characterizations of her opponents' views are underdeveloped, and it would be nice to see more connections made to other scholars dealing with the same kinds of issues. She does, to be sure, discuss the claims of opponents such as Daniel Callahan, Francis Fukuyama, Hans Jonas, Leon Kass, and others. But more thorough discussion of the relevant literature would be welcome; there are just twenty-eight bibliographic entries (for twenty-two authors) in this 230-page book.

Despite these criticisms, The Triple Helix possesses several useful and innovative features. The mapping out of theories of persons, agency, and moral worth is interesting.  The discussion of grief subtly reveals key features of the different views of persons (chapter 1). There is a novel and helpful discussion of "biofallacies" or informal errors in reasoning in bioethical contexts (pp. 126-136). Most importantly, Bellantoni's emphasis on lived, concrete experience, emotions, and social relations as essential to our sense of personhood, identity, and moral value is a welcome perspective in bioethics.

 

© 2013 William A. Bauer

 

William A. Bauer, Ph.D., is a Teaching Assistant Professor of Philosophy at North Carolina State University, with research and teaching interests in metaphysics, philosophy of science, and bioethics.


Share

Welcome to MHN's unique book review site Metapsychology. We feature over 7900 in-depth reviews of a wide range of books and DVDs written by our reviewers from many backgrounds and perspectives. We update our front page weekly and add more than thirty new reviews each month. Our editor is Christian Perring, PhD. To contact him, use one of the forms available here.

Can't remember our URL? Access our reviews directly via 'metapsychology.net'


Metapsychology Online reviewers normally receive gratis review copies of the items they review.
Metapsychology Online receives a commission from Amazon.com for purchases through this site, which helps us send review copies to reviewers. Please support us by making your Amazon.com purchases through our Amazon links. We thank you for your support!


Join our e-mail list!: Metapsychology New Review Announcements: Sent out monthly, these announcements list our recent reviews. To subscribe, click here.

Interested in becoming a book reviewer for Metapsychology? Currently, we especially need thoughtful reviewers for books in fiction, self-help and popular psychology. To apply, write to our editor.

Metapsychology Online Reviews

Promote your Page too

Metapsychology Online Reviews
ISSN 1931-5716